Sunday, December 6, 2009

Institutional protection

Scott Horton over at Harper's reports that the Obama DOJ has filed a brief on behalf of John Yoo in Padilla v Yoo. According to Horton, the brief argues that there are only 3 basic routes by which a lawyer at the DOJ can be held accountable for his official actions. All three routes depend, in essence, on the authority of the DOJ itself, which means that the DOJ is crimainally liable if and only if it finds itself to be so. Needless to say, this is an exceedingly low standard given any institution's inclination to protect itself.

Horton concludes:

The Holder Justice Department’s brief can only be squared with prior DOJ arguments this way: foreign lawyers in foreign Justice Departments have no immunity and can be held accountable, but lawyers who work for us have absolute immunity from any meaningful form of accountability. The path to a renewal of the criminal misconduct of the Bush years is being prepared right now. And Obama Justice Department lawyers are doing the work.


Read More...

Wednesday, November 4, 2009

Convictions and dismissals

Today we learned that Italy has convicted 23 Americans (in absentia) in association with their role in rendering a Muslim cleric from the streets of Milan. This is a pyrrhic victory of sorts, since the fugitive Americans will not in all likelihood spend a minute in jail. This is in large measure due to the U.S. government's incessant political pressure, grounded on the belief that it can do whatever it wants in the name of combatting terrorism. This belief reared its ugly head yesterday when the Second Court of Appeals threw out a case brought on by another torture victim of American rendition policy, Maher Arar. His case is familiar to anyone who follows these things. A Canadian citizen, picked up at JFK on a tip from te Canadian government, and inexplicably (unjustifiably) rendered to Syria where he was summarily tortured for about a year. The trip to Syria is not inexplicable if one recognizes the America's unaccountable desire to do whatever is 'necessary' to gather intelligence information. As it turns out, as it often does in these types of cases, the initial tip was ungrounded, and Arar had nothing to do with anything.

Now, evidently, the majority believed that to do otherwise than to dismiss the case would be an egregious form of judicial activism, since Congress has not explicitly penned law prohibiting this particular activity. It's not clear to me on what grounds they say this, since there exists any number of statutes under which a prosecutor could bring the culprits to justice. After all, isn't conspiracy to torutre a crime, on the books. The majority must be asking for something  else, namely, the green light by the Exectuve to prosecute its own members. Needless to say, we're still waiting for that. But on the ever useful charge of judicial activism, we can submit, on the contrary, that it is the grossest form of judicial activism to give, as this dismissmal does, carte blanche to a government gone wild. No one but the American government feels the need to dispute the facts of the Arar case, his unquestioned innocence, not even the Canadian government, which has already admitted culpability and settled with Arar. Yet, we continue to our ostrich policies from the highest levels of government down to the citizen on the street who 'just wants the government to protect him'. Well, perhaps Arar believed the same thing, that is, until he lived through the hell that comes from allowing flawed people to possess unchecked and unaccountable power. Do we all have to live through the same before we recognize the flaw here? Is our imagination and historical sense that weak? 

Before we raise our hands in salute of the Italians over the Americans, we should note that, in the Italian judgment today, 3 Italians were acquitted on the grounds that their conviction would divulge state secrets. So, there we go again.  

Read More...

Saturday, October 3, 2009

The top ten things you didn't know about Iran

I found Juan Cole's list helpful. Take a look.

Read More...

Monday, August 31, 2009

Why our media is lame

Paul Krugman runs down the reasons why media coverage of health care reform is lame. Basically, the reasons can be extended indefinitely to the coverage of any significant policy issue.

We've taken a shot at explaining this here. In the end, the idea is that many journalists are either too dumb or too cowardly to handle these issues. But, we shouldn't forget either that sometimes journalism is an unreasonably dangerous enterprise, and that our culture of violence (e.g. sending death threats to journalists who write intelligently about health care) plays a significant but often invisible role as well.

Read More...

Friday, August 28, 2009

Newly released OLC memos

Jack Balkin offers us a quick summary of various parts (new memos here). Nothing new, but every time I look at yet another one of these memos, I just can't believe what I'm seeing. What is the meaning of the rule of law if can be subverted so easily and its violators left free to roam and defended?.

Read More...

Sunday, August 9, 2009

The Responsibility to Protect

Noam Chomsky's take on the responsibility to protect. As always with Chomsky, an informative and interesting read. We've taken on this topic here and here.

Read More...

Wednesday, August 5, 2009

The Collapse of the Prison System

Yesterday the right-wing philosophy that has ruled the US prison system for the last decades received a long deserved blow. A panel of federal judges issued a mandate to reduce the total number of inmates in the state of California in more than 25% in a period of two years. Notwithstanding future appeals, the decision is the culmination of a long process of deterioration of the prison system in California, once the envy of other US states and nations. Currently the designed capacity of the system is roughly doubled and inmates are accommodated in hallways in makeshift beds.

The consequences of this overpopulation are both cruel and unusual. Inmates spend most of the time locked up as the only way to avoid fights and riots. Contagious diseases spread rapidly among inmates and estimates speak of one death per week due to lack of medical assistance. Human Rights advocates have been warning about severe constitutional violations for years but their cries have faded amid the tough-on-criminals mentality dominating the country. Finally, after years of struggle, the federal justice has come through and ordered an end to these abominations based on the Cruel and Unusual Punishment clause of the 8th Amendment.

This is the first official acknowledgement of the insurmountable failure of the philosophy that has dominated the country since the 80s. It might mark a turning point in the history of the prison system. But dissident voices have been around for a while and the debate has been shaping quietly in the background. The collapse of the system has been documented in almost every front. The rates of incarceration have skyrocketed in the last three decades and starting a few years ago one in every 100 adults in the US is in jail. Moreover, it is wholly unclear whether these costs have produced benefits, for the US leads the developed world in homicide rates.

On the other side of the Atlantic Ocean, in Holland, the prison system has also been the subject of intense debate. However, the problem there is one the US wishes it had. The Dutch government has been trying to close 8 prisons for lack of inmates while the Right has tried to persuade the public of the need to put more people in jail. The cost of the initiative will be 1,200 layoffs. Even so, the Right has been unable to stop it. This strikes me as a bit bizarre. On this side of the Atlantic it is always the politicians who are trying to temper down the thirst for blood in the public, not the other way around.

Holland’s problem is envied by others. But things did not always go well for the Dutch prison system. Only a decade ago Holland had followed the American trail and was beset by an overpopulation problem. But they reacted in time and avoided embarrassment. Since then they have increased paroles, implemented electronic surveillance, worked on rehabilitation and increased community service. Plus, undeniably Holland’s eccentric soft-drug policies have had some impact—though not enough to fully account for the phenomenon. In striking contrast with the US, in Holland one of every 1,000 people is in jail.

On a philosophical vein, it is particularly interesting to speculate about the roots of the American mentality with regard to incarceration. Tough-on-criminals policies have been championed by Right-wing groups, usually affiliated with religious views, and echoed by the masses (e.g. 80% of Americans support the death penalty). The explanation of this mentality in terms of the notion of free will is thus natural.

It is plain that religious doctrines usually rely on a substantial notion of free will. But aside from the metaphysical debate, the notion performs double duty in shaping the tough-on-criminals mentality. On the one hand, because individuals are perceived as essentially free, religious doctrines place the whole responsibility for their action on them. There is no need to look at environmental conditions to explain crime: it is simply the criminal’s choice. On the other hand, this has been abetted by the deterrent effect that is expected to ensue from this mentality. Whether or not offenders are fully responsible for their actions, if we hold them fully responsible by having no consideration with them, people in a position to commit crime will have to weigh their chances against this assumption which should deter them from taking criminal action.

But the truth is (as everybody knows except most Americans) that criminals don’t have free will. And this is not a metaphysical statement: criminals are determined by their upbringing, opportunities and even chance. Without a doubt social conditions are causally responsible for the production of crime (as for the production of science, literature, etc). To the extent society causally participates in the production of these evils, it shares the moral responsibility with the wrongdoer for her wrongdoings.

One can ignore reality as much as one wants—even with the hope that ignoring it will magically end crime. But reality is stubborn and ignores those who ignore it. By imprisoning all offenders the US has incapacitated them. But at the same time it has deprived them of the main source of rehabilitation: society. Criminals are not free to choose crime but neither are they free to choose rehabilitation. For too long has the US seen prisons not as functional parts of society but as ostracization facilities. The strategy of ignoring the conditions that produce crime has yielded the expected results: overcrowded prisons and no significant decline in crime. It is time for a change.

Read More...

Wednesday, July 29, 2009

Justification for facilitating torture

The case of the APA and its members who participated in coercive interrogations.

When I read about psychologists who participated in the Bush administration approved interrogation/torture sessions, I recoil in contempt. The contempt is heightened when I read that, since 2002, the American Psychological Association (APA) has effectively condoned and offered justifications for its members’ participation. Is my attitude justified?

Some say no. They do so on the basis of a counterfactual claim: interrogations would have been worse for detainees had it not been for psychologists’ participation. This argument uses the following standard for ethical action: doing something is justified if doing it leads to better outcomes than not doing it. Applied to our psychologists’ participation in torturous interrogation, we can respond, Really? Their participation led to torture and the claim is that without them matters would have been worse. Really, worse than being tortured?

Even if we grant that there are degrees of torture and that psychologists’ participation mitigated the degree of torture, the counterfactual claim is specious because it uses the wrong baseline for comparison. If I torture you less than someone else would have, then that results in a better state of affairs; but, it obviously can’t be used to justify what I am doing. As an aside, compare a similarly specious argument often made for paying the minimum conceivable wage to third-world workers: if I didn’t bring my business over there, they would be unemployed; therefore, since $1/day is better than the nothing they would have gotten, that’s what I’m justified in paying.

At the very least, then, a comparative claim used to justify action must use as a baseline not how things are or would have been without the action, but rather how things would have been if I had acted in all the ways I could have acted. In the case of the torturer, assuming she can stop torturing, that would represent the best outcome (in the case of the entrepreneur, a better outcome would be to pay the just amount which is certainly more than $1/day), and what she does in fact do can be justified only if it is better than that. So, a better standard of justification would be this: my action is justified if doing it is better than anything else that I could have done. I’m not saying that this is the correct standard, but we can use it for our present purposes of evaluating justification for facilitating torture.

We can begin by looking at a brief history of the APA’s ethics code that is relevant to conflict between law and professional ethics. We can note that prior to 2001, the APA’s ethics policy suggested that conflicts be ‘responsibly resolved’ by the psychologist. This open-endedness left it open to the psychologist to follow her conscience in potentially violating positive law. Post 9/11, the policy was revised to read that obeying the law, irrespective of its content, would be sufficient for its members ethical standing. [For a more detailed discussion of the APA’s ethical standards, see Kenneth S. Pope’s, Ph.D., ABPP and Thomas G. Gutheil’s, M.D. article, here.]

Let’s now think of the culpability of individual psychologists and their role in torturous interrogations. If their participation is to be justified, they must claim that their participation leads to better outcomes than anything else they could have done. Is this plausible? The director of the APA’s ethics office, Stephen Behnke, argues for the presence of psychologists as follows:

APA frames a role that psychologists have unique training to fill: the role of observing interrogations in order to guard against ‘behavioral drift’ on the part of interrogators. Behavioral drift, which may arise in high stress situations where there is insufficient ethical guidance or oversight, involves a deviation from professionally and ethically acceptable behavior and so may lead to coercive interrogation techniques. Psychologists, as experts in human behavior, are trained to observe and intervene to prevent behavioral drift.
On this view, the chief benefit of psychologists’ participation lies in their ethical and professional competencies, which competencies can be used to thwart coercion by morally drifting interrogators. I don’t know why Behnke believes psychologists possess particular ethical dispositions and/or competencies, but even if they were uniquely trained in that regard, by the APA’s own ethical standards discussed above, if CIA interrogators ‘legally’ coerced information, no psychologist would have authority to intervene into or report such coercion. The official policy belies the individual justification. Now, if even if we are to imagine a heroic psychologist who bucked the law, this doesn’t absolve the other psychologists who not only ‘monitored’ interrogations but devised, shaped, and directed an entire interrogation regime. This describes the roles of Bruce Jessen and Col. Morgan Banks who are both believed to have deployed their expertise in evading interrogation to develop the C.I.A’s and military’s S.E.R.E interrogation program (survival, evasion, resistance and escape). Can we say of such a psychologist that his participation is better than anything else he could have done?

Suppose neither had participated at all, as surely was open to them, then an entire regimen of coercive interrogations would have been eliminated from existence. And surely that outweighs any conceivable benefit, if such there be, of their actual participation. Behnke might retort that the way the two devised their interrogation regime led to safer methods than would have been available without them. Even if this is true (I’m highly skeptical), it uses the specious comparative benchmark discussed above. Given that their methodology has been established to be torturous, then the correct standard of comparison is not whether without them the CIA would have invented more torturous methods, but rather whether they could have devised effective interrogation methods that shunned any hint of coercion. By the many accounts of experienced FBI interrogators, the most effective method does not involve coercion, and we can surmise that both Jessen and Banks could have built a program around that truth.

Let’s leave aside the case of individuals and turn to the topic of institutional responsibility for facilitating torture. We can note firstly that, in the context of political policy and as compared to individuals, institutions have a far broader range of counterfactual actions available to them. This is partially because they are responsible for many of the rules under which individuals must act and partially because of the great causal powers institutions have in the modern world. This is an often neglected fact and, in my opinion, it implicates institutions in a broader range of responsibilities than is normally acknowledged. We need to keep this in mind when we assess the APA’s actions and omissions.

We know that around 2006 after reporting made clear the coercive nature of U.S. interrogations, the Amercian Medical Association and the American Psychiatric Association both issued prohibitions on its members from even being present at interrogations. Against this background, how should we assess the APA’s insistence on the benefits of psychologists’ participation. Given the existing ban by the AMA and the Am Psychiatric Assoc., the APA arguably could have put a stop to the whole sordid mess by following suit. Here’s why: as mentioned above, it is continually argued, both by the heads of the APA and military brass, that participation by psychologists is essential to keeping interrogations safe. Their absence, then, would entail unsafe interrogations. Therefore, at the very least, the APA’s prohibiting member participation would have put considerable political pressure on the administration to discontinue these, by their own lights, unsafe interrogations. So, this is a conceivable, even probable, counterfactual outcome, one which we can use to assess the goodness of the actual outcome. What was the actual outcome? Detainee deaths and psychologically broken human beings. By the standard set out above, the APA’s actions were unjustified, and it should be found culpable for torture.

The issue of individual and institutional culpability for the torture that took place under U.S. control is a complex problem. Nevertheless, the only argument I’ve seen defending the participation by APA members is specious, and the blame goes to the individual psychologists who participated in coercive interrogations but also, and perhaps to an even greater degree, the professional association which endorsed such participation.

Read More...

Saturday, July 25, 2009

One thought too many

We've all lived through Dick Cheney's outrageousness. Alongside his grim reaper Addington and legal waterboy John Yoo, he's perpetrated many grievances against America's reputation and standing in the world--not to mention against human beings.

But this one makes me angry. The New York Times reports that in 2002 Cheney and his cohorts tried to persuade Bush that military action in an American city was justified. Evidently, sleeper cells were on his mind and nothing short of military action could appease him. In contrast to his almost too cool public appearances, this grim episode proves how absolutely unhinged Cheney was during this time period. To be sure, in 2002 danger was in the air, and we wanted our public officials to be acutely sensitive to the very real possibility that more strikes on domestic soil was immanent. Nevertheless, to contemplate something so drastic in a case where more or less nothing was at stake, demonstrates the underlying paranoia which had seized his mind. Of course, the military strike never took place, evidently due to Bush's cooler, more reasonable mind (sic!). But the fact that it was even seriously deliberated evinces what Bernard Williams once quipped as 'one thought too many'.

Read More...

Tuesday, July 21, 2009

Honduras' Dilemma: Does pacifism still make sense?

When is the use of force justifiable? Is violence ever called for in a political conflict? These are questions the international community has been putting off for days in relation to Honduras. It just looks bad for an international actor to appear before the world supporting violence in a country devastated by poverty. On the contrary, pacifism would seem to always represent reason and temperance. But this can’t be true. For human beings act based on expectations about how their fellows will behave and if pacifism were a reliable expectation then others would unjustly capitalize on it. Some of this seems to be going on in Honduras.

The international community has had much patience with Micheletti’s de facto government. First, the OAS unanimously condemns the coup and demands the restoration of the constitutional order. Next, Honduras is suspended from the organization no longer qualifying for credits from the IADB and the World Bank. Then President Oscar Arias of Costa Rica (a Nobel Peace laureate) convinces the de facto government to negotiate with deposed president Zelaya in order to bridge the gap. Finally, after Arias’ effort proves fruitless, Arias and Isulza manage to cool off Zelaya and convince the parts to engage in a second round of negotiations in Costa Rica. Zelaya was ready to go back to Honduras and call for a popular revolt, bloodshed to follow.

At this point it seems unlikely that Arias’ negotiations will restore Zelaya to office. But anything short of that would create a horrible precedent. Powerful political groups in Latin American countries would learn that they can navigate the international pressure—after all, Honduras could, being the 3rd poorest country in the region. This would be a hotbed for political instability in a continent with a terrible record in this respect.

But unless the people of Honduras kicks Micheletti out of office by force, it seems that the de facto government is planning to get away with their goal (i.e. holding on until the end of the year where elections are scheduled). It seems likely at this point that nothing Arias or Insulza does is going to persuade them of restoring Zelaya to the presidency. This seems to be non-negotiable for Micheletti. On the other hand, the international community can not possible accept anything short of Zelaya's resitution. Hence, we have stalemate, and one that favors the de facto government.

Zelaya’s insistence on peace plays in Micheletti’s favor for their strategy seems to be holding on to power while letting time go by. It was worth trying but dialogue is wearing out and, what’s worse, the de facto government is cynically benefitting form this status quo. Shortly there will be no time to loose and the people of Honduras will have to make a choice. It’ll be either violence or Micheletti.

Read More...

Wednesday, July 15, 2009

In praise of courage and in contempt of cowardice

No one can reasonably expect an individual to risk their lives to track down the truth. Even if courage is a virtue and its expression an essential part of being human, the degree of courage manifested in activists and journalists who endanger themselves to reveal a truth lies beyond duty.

Although we cannot reasonably demand it, such courage always draws the admiration and praise of those who witness it.

The New York Times reported today on an exemplary case, that of human rights activist, Natalya Estemirova. It is a chilling story implicating the Chechen president and Estemerova, his implacable gadfly. Estemerova had made a habit of reporting on human rights abuses in Chechnya, and in the meanwhile angering the powers that be to the extent that they openly threatened her. Estemerova had won the prize Anna Politkovskaya, named after another journalist who made a habit of courageously questioning political authority. Here's a link to an article she wrote shortly prior to her assassination. The article indicates her consciousness that her life would be short. And yet there's a sense of calmness, as if she were writing about her own impending death from the perspective of a journalist covering her own life. She writes that the authorities want her to pretend that certain things she saw did not happen, and responds somewhat curiously, "How can I forget when it did happen?" This is curious only because this sort of forgetfulness is constantly on display in others, and I'll turn to examples of that shortly.

But the incapacity to forget, in particular the inability to will oneself to forget the truth, is a kind of virtue, I would say an expression of the highest virtue: to be unable to do the bad. Estemirova possessed this character trait as well. It was said that she couldn't quit her work, that she was burning up inside over it. This is true even though she faced the realization that her death would mean that her 15 year old daughter would be left alone.

We can turn now to the capacity to forget the truth, and unfortunately it is on full display in certain American journalists who not only are able to forget, they urge others to forget as well. Glenn Greenwald has been at the forefront of highlighting the activities of these journalists and his most recent exemplar is Chuck Todd who 'reports' on the White House for NBC. You see, Todd stands against investigations into the Bush administration's war crimes, their role in the abduction, incarceration, torture and deaths of detainees. To be fair, he has a reason for his stand: such investigations would distract Obama from what truly important, namely, pushing through health care reform and the economy.

Aside from the curiosity of hearing a self-described journalist criticize and attempt to undermine the search to find the truth, we are left with a sense that Todd simply does not, and most likely cannot, recognize the role of the journalist is not to concoct reasons that obscure government malfeasence. Todd is the anti-Estemirova. While she can't help but search out the truth, he cannot will himself to seek it. In the place of the search for truth, Todd portrays himself as a political realist, as an oracle for which investigations will and will not work. Instead of being an investigator, he is a prognosticator. Since he predicts that torture investigations will become, as he says, a 'political football', he deems them a waste of time and detrimental to America's reputation (!?).

But even if this were all true, what does it have to do with whether a journalist should spend her time tenaciously getting to the bottom of the matter? Todd conveniently, and by all indications sincerely, believes it is not reasonable to demand that a journalist risk anything, for prediction is a risk-free game. I started by saying that it is not reasonable to demand that anyone risk their lives for truth, but it surely is a expression of cowardice to be a risk-free journalist. If we praise Estemirova, Politskovskaya and the like, we must contemn the likes of Todd, for the latter are worse than useless: they obstruct the good works of the former.

Read More...

Friday, July 10, 2009

Shock and Shame in NY

After the month-long stalemate in the NY State Senate caused by defecting senator Pedro Espada, the distinguished New York congressmen have finally found a way out that tops the embarrassment of their constituency. They have decided to offer Espada (yes, the betrayer!!!) the majority leadership in order to draw him back from the Republican caucus. Yes, believe it. This is not a Buñuel movie or a crooks novel, it is our honorable New York State Senate right now. Because the majority leadership is the highest senate position, short of their wives it is not clear what Republicans can offer Espada to woo him back.

Read More...

Monday, July 6, 2009

Lessons for Honduras

As democratically elected president Manuel Zelaya was flying back to Honduras this morning thousands marched to the airport to welcome him. But the warm encounter never took place. Zelaya’s plane was not allowed to land by army vehicles occupying the runaway and the crowd was dispersed by security forces loyal to the de facto authorities of Honduras. The reported result is a 10-year old dead and many injured while the unlawful regime holds on to power for another day.

This is the 3rd or 4th attempt to restore the rule of law in Honduras by peaceful means. A few days ago, Secretary General of OAS, José Miguel Insulza, visited the country in a last-ditch attempt to reconcile positions before expelling Honduras from the organization. Insulza made a career in Chilean politics for his tough political intelligence in handling difficult ideological conflicts (e.g. Isulza was Chile’s minister of foreign affairs when Pinochet was arrested in London at Garzon’s request). And in this case he was able to quickly work out a unanimous repudiation of Honduras’ coup by all American countries—a remarkable achievement if one dwells on Zelaya’s affiliation with Hugo Chávez. However, the de facto authorities of Honduras have proved recalcitrant.

Though the international response has been dramatically different, the internal circumstances that have led to this coup are reminiscent of Venezuela’s 2002 coup or, going further back, of Chile’s 1973 coup. In all three cases there was a democratically elected president (cf. Chavez 1998, Allende 1970) pushing significant reforms to the constitution. The reforms are either targeted at favoring the lower classes or the government quite explicitly vows to do so and the reforms aim at perpetuating the regime. The higher classes are terrified that they are going to loose their privileges, be them legitimate or not.

The result of this conjunction of circumstances is invariably an extreme polarization of the society at hand and eventually social turmoil. In Chile it led to Pinochet’s 17-year dictatorship marked by atrocious violations of human rights. In 2002 the international conditions were significantly different and Carmona’s coup in Venezuela did not survive a week. The international conditions are even less favorable to the de facto government in Honduras but it remains to be seen if Zelaya’s popular support has enough strength to bring him back to office, as the social movement in Venezuela did with Chavez in 2002.

The case of Honduras is also important in another respect: it is the first time since the coup in Venezuela in 2002 that a Latin American country takes an unconstitutional line to resolve its own conflicts. After decades of political turmoil, it seemed that Latin America had finally found a lasting constitutional equilibrium. The coup in Honduras brings out fears of a dark past.

But it also invites reflection on the limits of democracy and its mechanisms of conflict resolution. It seems hard to contest that Zelaya’s government was democratic. However, it was partial to the poor in the social struggle between classes. The economic and political elites felt threatened and feared what they regarded as an illegitimate rewriting of the social contract. But they were outnumbered and the government would eventually be able to achieve this goal. It is understandable (though not for that reason justifiable) that the elites were going to wave their power against what they regarded as unjust and unlawful.

Because the cases of Chile, Venezuela and Honduras led to the same outcome irrespective of the diverse international conditions (cf. the coup in Chile was supported by the US) one could infer that a fracture of these dimensions at the heart of a society almost invariably leads to an unconstitutional outcome. And this is unsurprising if one looks at the problem through the lens of social contract theories. After all, cooperation is the glue that keeps society together. When different factions begin looking at each other suspiciously, not as teammates working for the well-being of all but as ruthless competitors for the scarce resources, all trust is lost. Scruples and knightliness quickly become obsolete in the game of survival and turmoil ensues.

For their own sake countries need to find social arrangements perceived as fair and beneficial by all. This is an old lesson drawn by many philosophers and political scientists since at least Rousseau. But it remains as valid as ever. Honduras confirms it once more. May Honduras learn the lesson in the light of the unfortunate events of this week.

Read More...

Friday, July 3, 2009

Washington Post death watch

Wow. What is going on over at the Washington Post?


Evidently, the once proud newspaper attempted to solicit funds in exchange for access to its news division and editorial staff. The events were supposed to be in the form of self-styled 'salons'. According to the nature of things, the newspaper now vehemently denies any impropriety, citing that it would never compromise its news division's integrity: it was all a misunderstanding, the advertising flyer was not vetted, blah, blah, blah.

Via Politico: (the text of the solicitation)

Offered at $25,000 per sponsor, per Salon. Maximum of two sponsors per Salon. Underwriters’ CEO or Executive Director participates in the discussion. Underwriters appreciatively acknowledged in printed invitations and at the dinner. Annual series sponsorship of 11 Salons offered at $250,000 … Hosts and Discussion Leaders ... Health-care reporting and editorial staff members of The Washington Post ... An exclusive opportunity to participate in the health-care reform debate among the select few who will actually get it done. ... A Washington Post Salon ... July 21, 2009 6:30 p.m. ...

"Washington Post Salons are extensions of The Washington Post brand of journalistic inquiry into the issues, a unique opportunity for stakeholders to hear and be heard," the flier says. "At the core is a critical topic of our day. Dinner and a volley of ideas unfold in an evening of intelligent, news-driven and off-the-record conversation. ... By bringing together those powerful few in business and policy-making who are forwarding, legislating and reporting on the issues, Washington Post Salons give life to the debate. Be at this nexus of business and policy with your underwriting of Washington Post Salons.


Embarrassing at best. At worst, another nail in the coffin of the Washington Post. After the Dan Froomkin debacle, the powers that be are doing all they can to chase away their audience.




Read More...

Tuesday, June 30, 2009

Chile and human rights

Chile becomes the final country in S. America to ratify the Rome Statute. Among other things, this brings Chile in line with the international community on human rights norms involving genocide and crimes against humanity.

Read More...

Friday, June 26, 2009

Michael Jackson's Uncensored Obituary

Michael Jackson’s sudden death has drawn the world’s attention all at once onto him likely for the last time. Michael Jackson was unquestionably one of the most famous and admired music icons of the modern world, sharing that pantheon only with a few (e.g. Elvis Presley, The Beatles or Madonna, come to mind). He was a prodigy: a massive-media, pop-culture version of Mozart, only deeply admired worldwide by the rich and the poor alike. And while I understand the fans’ admiration, I myself never was one of his followers. Perhaps because of the objectivity this might confer me, throughout the course of Michael Jackson’s life I couldn’t help the feeling of pity for him. For while Michael Jackson is the prototype of the music idol, whom all the kids and teenagers (and sometimes even a little older ones) imitate and see as the role model, for this very reason he also is an example of the worst abominations of our times. Because he is the pinnacle of modern fame, he also exemplifies in the worst form possible how public attention can corrode a human being.

Michael Jackson was a great pop musician and dancer but he was also a victim of his time. Physically and psychologically Michael Jackson was a freak. He was an eternal child trapped in childish dreams completely unable to understand a world that worshipped him. Now everybody remembers him but only a few days ago he was alone, locked in his Neverland world. In reality, this was not just a bad ending, it was also a bad beginning. Michael Jackson was alone for most of his life incapable of leading a normal life behind the scenes. But this was not the fault of his family and friends. Nor was it his own fault—how could it be, if he never had a choice? Again, Michael Jackson is a product of his times, the result of the unconditional love and admiration of millions who followed him since he was a boy. His case should give us food for thought regarding the values of modern society and the relentless aspiration to fame. Goodbye Michael, may you find peace finally.

Read More...

Monday, June 22, 2009

death of the Washington Post

I used to read the Washington Post because of its good coverage of Guantanamo and detainee treatment. But I just heard (been tucked away in a technology-free zone) about its firing of Dan Froomkin and well that spells the death of the WaPost for me.

As usual, Glenn Greenwald has some insightful points to make on a topic he writes about quite often. In short: Froomkin was too much of a real journalist for the Washington Post's editorial board to handle, because according to it, the function of journalism is to cater to the prevailing political masters.

Read More...

Wednesday, June 17, 2009

Yoo civil lawsuit allowed to proceed

See here. Also, see the Washington Post's editorial criticizing the decision. Its argument is summed up by the following:

Moreover, Mr. Yoo provided legal opinions on what he believed the law allowed the executive to do, but he did not make the final policy decisions. Allowing Mr. Padilla's case to proceed could have a chilling effect on the ability of government lawyers to give candid, good-faith advice for fear of being held personally liable.
I've addressed the distinction between advice and policy here. In Yoo's case, that distinction doesn't apply in the usual way, and the Washington Post's editorial is, once again, an utter failure.


Read More...

Friday, June 12, 2009

New York, 3rd World State

I have vast experience in 3rd World politics and can testify that the spectacle we have witnessed in the New York State Senate this week easily matches the worst episodes of corruption I have known about in Latin America or Africa. Two Democratic senators were apparently "persuaded" by a tycoon (who is not even part of the senate or any political party but who recently financed some important democratic state campaigns) to defect from the Democratic party allowing Republicans to seize control of the closely divided chamber.

This billionaire patron was indignant at the Democratic majority because of their plan to raise taxes on the rich to compensate the spiraling state deficit. Unable to deter them from going ahead with their plan, he opted for the healthy alternative of inviting a couple of senators with God knows what incentives to move to the opposite party.

In case this is not fishy enough, one of the defecting senators had been drawn to the Democratic side not long ago with promises of power and protection from the countless charges of corruption that he has faced lately. The other defecting senator was recently indicted with charges of having stabbed his companion.

You gotta wonder what the heck is going on in New York. The current governor, David Paterson, replaced the elected governor, Eliot Spitzer, who resigned last year after being linked to a prostitution ring. Like in the worst crooks movies, New York politics seems to be dominated by an underworld of corruption and personal interest. Democrats have taken legal measures against the Republican coup and a judge is set to deliberate on the issue next week. Whatever the outcome of this mess, the situation illustrates the need to clean the sordid political landscape of New York State as soon as possible.

Read More...

Monday, June 8, 2009

Boumediene 2: Bush 0

This is what Lakhdar Boumediene's homemade t-shirt reads, as related in his recent interview with ABC News. It refers to his two victories over the morally bankrupt Bush administration who willfully and needlessly kept him at Guantanamo for 7 years. The first victory was SCOTUS's judgment in Boumediene v. Bush which enabled him to get judicial review. The other was U.S. District Judge Richard J. Leon's decision to free him upon reviewing the 'thin reed' of evidence the administration had against him.

Boumediene makes the following remarkable statement about the duration of his detainment:

"The first month, okay, no problem, the building, the 11 of September, the people, they are scared, but not 7 years. They can know whose innocent, who's not innocent, who's terrorist, who's not terrorist," he said.

"I give you 2 years, no problem, but not 7 years."

It's remarkably generous to offer 2 years of your life for a gross mistake (assuming that it's just that), especially given the credible charge of being tortured whilst incarcerated. But leaving that aside, Boumediene's point should strike a mortal blow to any proponent of executive privilege who wants to assert that the executive is better qualified than any other branch of government to handle matters of war--a standard talking point for the right. After 7 years, the executive could not (or would not) determine Boumediene's innocence. On the other hand, it took Judge Leon only 5 months after Boumediene v Bush to sift through all the evidence and render his judgment (PDF file). In which institution would you place more trust?

Read More...

Friday, June 5, 2009

Berlusconi's Innocent Villa

After Veronica Lario, Belusconi's wife, filed for divorced accusing him of shameless sexual corruption, Italian paparazzi caught the Italian president enjoying an "innocent" afternoon (as he himself referred to the pictures) with some of his friends (here).

Read More...

Saturday, May 30, 2009

On American Ignorance

An interesting article on a topic we've visited before.

Read More...

Tuesday, May 26, 2009

The Morality of Obama's Guantanamo Plan

No doubt Obama’s plan to close the Guantanamo Base prison is a step forward in fighting the threat of terrorism. Dick Cheney resents this fact for it entails that his own decisions were steps backward. But at this point who cares what Cheney says other than his reactionary cronies? After all, Cheney’s arguments do not pass a minimum test of cogency and vision. Nonetheless Obama’s plan brings to the surface a fundamental question that had been overshadowed by the numerous obscenities of the Bush administration. This is the question of preemptive incarceration.

Obama’s plan consists in transferring Guantanamo detainees to maximum-security prisons within the US borders but it does not include a discernible answer for the legal abominations these cases represent. During the presidential campaign, McCain warned Obama of the intricacies the new president was going to find once he had access to classified information on the Guantanamo detainees. And for all his gaffes, the facts seem to confirm McCain’s forecast. For what was once determination in Obama to close Guantanamo has now turned into feeble compromise. Barring an unexpected change of course, it seems that Obama’s plan is only symbolic vindication: Guantanamo detainees will be transferred to American soil but kept in the legal limbo they’ve dwelled for years.

God knows what information Obama and his legal advisors have come across in revising the Guantanamo cases. But I think it unlikely that anything short of imminent danger for the country would have persuaded Obama of the need to continue with this legal farce. So let’s suppose for the sake of the argument that Guantanamo detainees represent an imminent threat to the US. If they had not yet committed any punitive action, is it lawful and/or moral to restrain them?

Here we find the two traditional frameworks in philosophy of punishment giving opposite advice. According to the Utilitarian framework, punishment is morally justified by its beneficial consequences. Utilitarians typically mention the incapacitation of the offender as among these consequences. Thus it would appear permissible, according to this framework, to incarcerate an individual on the sole grounds that he or she represents a threat for the US.

The alternative to the Utilitarian framework is Retrubitivism. Roughly, Retributivism is the view that punishment is justified by an abstract balance representing our sense of justice. When somebody breaks the law he or she has upset that balance and punishment is required in order to restore it. It straightforwardly follows from this view that we are justified in punishing only those who have broken the law. Therefore, restraining Guantanamo detainees would be wholly immoral even if they are indeed a threat to the country and we know it, for they have yet to act on their impure intentions.

It would be presumptuous of me to attempt to adjudicate between these competing frameworks. Generations of philosophers have passed unable to do so. However, it is fair to say that even many Utilitarians, while rejecting the whole Retributive package, accept the idea that only the guilty should be punished. Guantanamo detainees cannot be guilty of anything yet as they have been denied the nowadays luxury of a due process. And having bad intentions is not recognized as a crime by any legal code. As a consequence, it seems really hard to reconcile Obama’s Guantanamo plan with any accepted morality of punishment.

Politicians are not only beholden to such abstractions as justice but also to their country. It seems therefore unlikely that Obama (or anybody for that matter) is going to clean this mess. No doubt politicians in positions of power have a responsibility to protect their country. But more importantly, the American electorate is extremely sensitive to the issue. Republicans have traditionally exploited the issue of national security to a point of absurdity. And Cheney as well as the Republican minority in Congress have made it clear that they will continue to pound it. This leaves the Obama administration with no margin to correct the abominations created by Republicans themselves.

As Nancy Pelosi has lately insisted, there is an important distinction to be drawn between those who caused this state of affairs and those who have failed to straighten it. There can be no doubt that Republicans fall in the former category and thus carry most of the responsibility for jeopardizing the Constitution of the US. However, they also carry some of the responsibility for politicizing the problem now in the hands of the new administration blocking any conceivable solution for it. As Eugene Robinson suggests, in history books hundreds of years from now Republicans will have to be charged with the decline of the US.

Read More...

Tuesday, May 19, 2009

Advice, policy and action

One major line of defense John Yoo offers for his role in torture relies on the distinction between advice and policy (authority to prescribe action). (See the prepared statement he made before his testimony to the House Judiciary Committee back in 2008).

The thought is that setting policy, but not giving advice, is related to action in a responsibility determining way. This is because policy not only endorses an action (as right/wrong, viable/unviable, legal/illegal), it motivates by being the reason for the action. In short, policy can be a constitutive part of an action which depends on it; it is the reason which explains the action. This connection explains why we tend to believe that if an action like torturing someone is wrong, then the authoritative policy which directly calls for it is also wrong.

On the face of it, advice is different. In an advisory role, the content of the advice is not taken to have motivational force. Additionally, I may not be advising you to do anything in particular but rather just laying out what I take to be your options. This is what John Yoo claims of his legal advice: it merely laid out an interpretation of legal options, and it was neither his intent nor within his authority to prescribe which options, if any, are to be taken. Yoo claims it follows that he cannot be held liable for the actions of those who were directed by policy to act in accordance with such advice. This is because, we can say, a ‘responsibility’ gap exists between advice and action, the gap filled by an independent judgment as to whether to follow the advice. So, if someone must be held accountable for the torture, it should be those who formulated the policy and carried it out. They have a direct responsibility bearing relationship to the vicious act.

Let’s examine the claim about advice. When someone asks for practical advice, it implies that he has not made up his mind on what to do. Typically, upon being offered a piece of practical advice, the advisee deliberates, takes the advice into consideration among all the other known considerations, and arrives at a decision about what to do. The process of deliberation arguably makes the advisee solely responsible for the ultimate decision. Plausibly, this shields the advisor from responsibility.

However, the conclusions are different when the advisor has practical authority over his advisee. Usually we distinguish between contexts of advice and authority, because advice is not often taken to be authoritative, but this is not a conceptual point, but rather just an expression of how we talk. When someone has practical authority over another, his pronouncements/directives/assertions possess preemptory status among the other reasons the advisee may have. That is, whatever other reasons the advisee may have, they are overruled (and are taken to be overruled) by the authority. In this context, when an advisor makes a pronouncement, he understands it to constrain and/or function as a sufficient reason for action.

What was the context in which Yoo wrote the OLC memo? As Yoo himself notes in his testimony before the Committee, his advice was requested in a very particular context: whether the recently (at the time) captured Abu Zubaydah could be subjected to enhanced interrogation techniques, given that such techniques, so Yoo claimed, would be extremely helpful to and desired by the executive.

But the relationship between executive and the OLC is not one of desire satisfaction, it is the latter’s job to constrain the actions of the former. This is confirmed by the particular institutional role the OLC occupies within the executive branch. The following statement from the OLC ‘best practices’ statement is relevant:

“Our Office is frequently called upon to address issues of central importance to the functioning of the federal Government, and, subject to the President’s authority under the Constitution, OLC opinions are controlling on questions of law within the Executive Branch” (emphasis added).

That is, should there be any dispute on how to understand (and hence how to obey) a law, OLC memos are preemptory. This applies to everyone in the executive branch, including the President.

This undermines John Yoo’s basic defense. Although his advice did not take the form of policy, it went beyond the typical function of advice to supply mere considerations for deliberation. Due to the institutional authority granted to him, his advice took on an imperative like form.

Given his knowledge of the advisee’s motivations (we already know of the ‘principals meetings’ during which this whole cabal got together to discuss strategies to implement torture), Yoo’s affirming advice must be recognized to be motivational—and hence a part of the advisee’s decision to formulate the torture policy. This is what makes him culpable for his advice.

Read More...

Tuesday, April 28, 2009

Torture and Pragmatism in Washington

If one focuses one can smell the reluctance in the political atmosphere to hold the Bush administration accountable for their systematic use of torture. This reluctance can be explained by various considerations such as the ferocious battle Republicans are likely to put up in Bush and Cheney’s defense; the subsequent loss of political capital for the Obama administration; etc. These are more or less practical difficulties. But there is, according to a Washington Post’s editorial, a matter of principle too.

The principle is that an incoming administration does not prosecute previous administrations for what they did “within the channels of government” as long as they did it for the sake of the country. In the absence of grounds to suspect selfish motivations we should measure the previous administration with a very loose bar (or, more precisely, a very loose legal code). This principle, the editorial claims, is a tradition in the US that has fostered cooperation between Democrats and Republicans and prevented them from seeking revenge for past political skirmishes. It prescribes that incoming administrations should scratch off the page and look the other way while doing so. Doing the opposite, the Post suggests, would encourage political vendetta and chaos.

Let us explore the implications of this argument.


First of all, the principle deprives high government officials of any kind of accountability. From the viewpoint of high government officials, there is no legal limit to how they can pursue the interest of the country. True, the country does have a constitution but if at some point it becomes an obstacle in seeking the interest of the country, the principle implies that high government officials can sidestep it without having to answer for that. But unless I’ve been confused all these years, the whole point of having a constitution is that nobody can’t ignore it when convenient, not even the president.

The reasons why you can’t ignore the Constitution are not mere patriotic mythology. The Constitution is literally the foundation of a country. It is the basic institutional framework that shapes what the nation is over and above a piece of land with inhabitants. Toying with the Constitution is therefore to discredit all the institutions of the nation including the nation as a whole. What can be a more serious threat to a nation than a massive loss of faith in it by its citizens, i.e. its own delegitimization? Is terrorism more dangerous?

But not only do fellow citizens lose faith in their country when they see their authorities manipulating the Constitution, so do international observers. The principle is completely oblivious to this fact. However, the US cannot possibly succeed in such an interdependent world as we witness today without forging honest alliances with other countries. Playing loose with the Constitution, as the principle prescribes, projects an image of unprincipled mercenaries in relentless pursue of their selfish interest. This is a hotbed for hatred and terrorism. Moreover, this makes it harder to find allies and, more importantly, to expect loyalty from them.

In fact, much of the mistrust toward the US in the Middle East and Latin America (to mention only a couple of cases) can arguably be explained by the systematic application of the principle. For example, the disclosure of private communications between Nixon and Kissinger in the 70s has revealed political plotting hardly reconcilable with the Constitution in their effort to stop the spread of Socialism in South America. One may debate the legitimacy of such a goal, but there can be no doubt that the inhumanity of the methods alongside the impunity of those who ordered them created a sensation of powerlessness and bitterness toward the US that has hindered cooperation with South American countries up to these days.

Aside from the implications of the principle, its motivation is also debatable. The risk the principle is design to ward off is that of permanent political vendetta and chaos as a result of giving incoming administrations permission to prosecute previous ones when their decisions were beside the Law. But should we assume, as the principle does, that every incoming administration is going to misuse their right to revise the previous one in order to get political benefit? Maybe—if there were no penalty for defamation. In legal systems where there are suitable penalties for defamation people make sure that they accuse others only when they have strong grounds to support their accusations. I don’t see why American politicians would be the exception.

I envision a much different outcome of dropping the principle. I believe the result would be that high government officials would have to be much more careful to stay within the limits of the Law. There would probably be some accusations here and there, some of them unjustified perhaps, but they would only serve to teach politicians to be impeccable during their time in office. In short, rather than vendetta and chaos, I think dropping the principle would encourage transparency and the rule of law.

Why then has the principle become a tradition in the US—as the Washington Post naively asserts? The fact that the reason offered by the Post is so dubious suggests less honorific motivations. The persistence of the principle could also be explained by a secret culture of extreme pragmatism in Washington. If politicians in Washington took the rule of Law as defeasible when governing requires it, the principle would serve as a secret code of etiquette to preserve that chance for future presidents and high government officials. In other words, incoming presidents would not seek legal measures against their predecessor, even when they deserved it, in order to be able to play that card themselves.

If this speculation were true, it would be quite serious. Pragmatism can be useful on occasion, but, taken to these extremes, it can also be sign that the spirit of the nation is in decline (cf. the last centuries of the Roman Empire). Obama seems to be of a different kind than most politicians in Washington. He seems clear and transparent, unaided by stratagem. Let’s hope that Obama will once for all drop the principle and restore a culture of transparency in Washington by going after the obvious violations to the Constitution that took place during Bush’s administration.

Matias Bulnes, NYC

Read More...

Thursday, April 23, 2009

Challenging Cheney

I don't believe the question of whether America's torture regime is legitimate rests on the question of its effectiveness in gathering intelligence.  Nevertheless, it is intelligible for someone to make that question the decisive question to ask and answer.  


Knowing this, and with his usual bravado, Cheney announced that he formally requested the release of classified memos which, he claims, conclusively demonstrate the effectiveness of torture in providing actionable intelligence.  In a NY Times Op-Ed, and in an apparent response to Cheney's bravado, Ali Soufan, the FBI agent who interrogated Abu Zubaydah, claims that valuable intelligence gathered from this interrogation arrived via traditional, i.e. non torturous, methods.  Additionally, he makes the following claims,
there was no actionable intelligence gained from using enhanced interrogation techniques on Abu Zubaydah that wasn’t, or couldn’t have been, gained from regular tactics...Defenders of these [torturous--mtn] techniques have claimed that they got Abu Zubaydah to give up information leading to the capture of Ramzi bin al-Shibh, a top aide to Khalid Shaikh Mohammed, and Mr. Padilla. This is false. The information that led to Mr. Shibh’s capture came primarily from a different terrorist operative who was interviewed using traditional methods. As for Mr. Padilla, the dates just don’t add up: the harsh techniques were approved in the memo of August 2002, Mr. Padilla had been arrested that May.
 If true, this would put the final nail in the coffin of the torture regime.  It yielded literally nothing of value, and we have come to the end of intelligible rationales for its existence.  And what is left but to conclude with Paul Krugman, if one hadn't already, that the authors of this regime are monsters.    

Read More...

Tuesday, April 21, 2009

Question of responsibility

I believe that there is a significant moral distinction between interrogators and those who legally authorized them to torture.

The difference is two-fold. First, the authors of torture regime are authors. They shaped and otherwise made possible the kinds of actions in question. Generally speaking, we believe that the authors of actions are chiefly responsible, and hence chiefly to blame, for them. On my understanding, the CIA frequently abstained from certain techniques and carried them out only after requests for legal guidance were returned in the affirmative. So, from what we know, the following counterfactual is true: were it not for the OLC memos and the political authority of Cheney’s office, America’s torture chambers would not have existed (I’m leaving aside the evidence that it existed in places other than Bagram, Abu Ghraib and Guantanamo). Secondly, there is a significant difference in authority and power between the two classes, and this can generate conditions of duress which can be mitigating and perhaps excusing. There was an incredible amount of pressure placed on the intelligence community to manufacture results, and given the structures of authority in place, that pressure could not have been just ignored—at least not without consequences.

To be sure, these two considerations alone won’t settle the whole question of responsibility if only because the interrogators aren’t automatons—they too author their own behaviors. This is quite clear in interrogation, since it leaves much room for maneuverability and hence deliberation—and all this needs to be decided upon, and hence authored, by each individual interrogator. Moreover, the degree of exerted pressure is unknown, and independently of that, it is difficult to imagine that it amounted to a form of duress which would be excusing.  In the end, one imagines, they could have walked away from the torture chambers and obeyed the Socratic doctrine to do no wrong intentionally.  


Nevertheless, with the question of blame left open for the interrogators, we can still make the comparative judgment that the degree of culpability is greater for the authors of the torture regime than for those who carried it out.  Another way of seeing this is to say that it was the legal duty of the interrogators to carry out legally authorized directives, but not the legal duty of the authors to write what they did.  In fact, as many lawyers have pointed out, the memos express legally incompetent advice.  Even if we don't share the latter judgment, the distinction in obligations offers yet another not insignificant dimension along which to damn the lawyers before the interrogators.         

I believe both points speak against the view, held by Spain’s attorney general, that if prosecutions are to go forward, they should be launched against individual interrogators and not the authors of the regime.  Obama has finally made it clear (even after his attack dog Rahm Emanuel suggested otherwise just last weekend) that he believes otherwise.  In response to questions this morning, he asserted that any investigation and prosecution of the torture authors will be, as it should be, the Attorney General's office to decide and pursue.  Hopefully, and as early indications of Holder already suggest, our AG is less politically driven than Spain's AG.      


Read More...

Friday, April 17, 2009

Flip-flop

Yesterday, Obama said that the failure to release the torture memos "could contribute to an inaccurate accounting of the past, and fuel erroneous and inflammatory assumptions about actions taken by the United States." This suggests that their eventual release should settle some questions. I suggested that this was a sort of preemptive attack on Spain's criminal investigations into who authorized what. Lo and behold, today, after just last week announcing that they would pursue indictments, Spanish prosecutors did a flip-flop. According to Spain's Attorney General, Cáandido Conde-Pumpido, any prosecution should focus on the interrogators, not the legal advisors. He therefore believes the case is flawed and does not recommend its pursuit. Evidently, the career prosecutors have been overruled.

Is there a connection between Obama's statement and the Spanish AG's decision? Inquiring minds want to know.

When asked by reporters about the case, Obama gave his standard, "I'm a strong believer that it's important to look forward and not backwards," claptrap. It's time he talk to the public like adults and offer a reasonably complete picture of his views on this matter. Leadership requires more than clever aphorisms; we need guidance and transparency.

Read More...

Wednesday, April 15, 2009

Uncovering and maintaining secrets

Update:

Obama has authorized the release of the 3 'torture memos'.  They are available here.  I've quickly gone through the memos, and there is very little redaction (although, there seems to be a page or two missing--I'm not sure of that though).  Obama also released a written statement about the memos.  Here is a relevant bit, explaining his reasoning:

...I believe that exceptional circumstances surround these memos and require their release.

First, the interrogation techniques described in these memos have already been widely reported. Second, the previous Administration publicly acknowledged portions of the program – and some of the practices – associated with these memos. Third, I have already ended the techniques described in the memos through an Executive Order. Therefore, withholding these memos would only serve to deny facts that have been in the public domain for some time. This could contribute to an inaccurate accounting of the past, and fuel erroneous and inflammatory assumptions about actions taken by the United States. 

In releasing these memos, it is our intention to assure those who carried out their duties relying in good faith upon legal advice from the Department of Justice that they will not be subject to prosecution. The men and women of our intelligence community serve courageously on the front lines of a dangerous world. Their accomplishments are unsung and their names unknown, but because of their sacrifices, every single American is safer. We must protect their identities as vigilantly as they protect our security, and we must provide them with the confidence that they can do their jobs.

Three points.  First, as I suggested in my original post, a refusal to release the memos would just be an exercise in failing to acknowledge what's already known.  Despite pressures to do otherwise, Obama recognized this.  Secondly, Obama seems to have found a politically intelligible position.  In releasing the memos, he's placating those who demand transparency in government; and, by ensuring interrogators not be prosecuted, he placates the career intelligence agents whose trust he requires.  Thirdly, the bit about fueling inflammatory and erroneous assumptions may have been a preemptive attack on the Spanish prosecutors who are seeking indictments of the authors of these memos.  The quest for indictments is surely inflammatory, but in what sense is it erroneous?  Surely, there is a distinction between the lawyers who drafted these memos and the interrogators who relied on their legal purport.  The legitimacy of the interrogators' actions rested entirely on the authority of these memos--and these lawyers knew exactly that when they penned them.

In his statement and in the context of a call to unity, Obama said that "this is a time for reflection, not retribution."  I think it would be retributive, in the sense of vengeful, to seek the prosecution of interrogators who relied on the legal advice of authorized lawyers.  This would be a mistake.  On the other hand, retribution, in the sense of retributive justice, has its legitimate place, because it is a constitutive part of applying the rule of law.  For several reasons, it would be a serious mistake to merely reflect on past illegal behaviors.  Firstly, retribution, and not mere reflection, is a more effective means to ensuring that these heinous power drunk behaviors don't occur in the future.  Secondly, irrespective of incentivizing future deliberations, the resentment caused by the torture regime will not just go away by reflection alone.  It is a truth about human beings that 'moral repair' or the achievement of normalizing relations between victim and victimizer requires punishment or, at the very minimum, a full account.  A victim can't get that through 'reflection'; s/he needs a social space in which truths are investigated and properly aired by trusted authorities.  It doesn't sound like Obama understands this, either because his optimism prevents it, or else his political radar signals that it is a political non-starter.       
----------------------------   
Spanish investigators are pressing ahead with their prosecution of the American torture crew, including Yoo, Addington and Gonzales. 

Apparently, adherence to the rule of law and the desire to uncover the truth about torture does not extend to the other side of the pond.  The Wall St. Journal reports that Obama is leaning towards keeping classified 3 'torture memos', ones which he previously promised he would disclose (not to mention that there is an outstanding court order for him to do so).  

To be sure, there exist various political reasons for maintaining darkness.  Chief amongst them, evidently, is Obama's desire to keep rank and file members of the CIA in the fold.  Fearing alienation, he is balancing citizen's need to know with his ability to maintain control over a key intelligence agency.  This is an intelligible desire.  

However, it is difficult to see how willfully maintaining darkness is a winning strategy, given the circumstances.  First, there is no end to the grief he is going to face should he align himself with this sordid past.  Secondly, the most credible source in existence on such matters, the Red Cross report, has already unequivocally asserted that torture took place under US hands.  And, we already know, more or less, the identities of the main players involved in authorizing this torture.  In keeping certain details secret, Obama would be doing little but failing to acknowledge what is already known.  Of course, it is not known to the larger public--and maybe that's what the triangulation is about--but ostrich-style politics can't coexist in the same world as the Google search bar.  In the Google world, knowledge is but a few keystrokes away, and maintaining secrets, especially when they have nothing to do with you, is a political loser.       

Read More...

Tuesday, April 14, 2009

Competing conceptions of human rights by MT Nguyen, The Empire, CA

What counts as a human rights violation? Or, alternatively, What counts as a fundamentally illegitimate government action?

These are very important questions. Answering them is a condition of our capacity to understand and critique political authority.

I think there are two basic and distinct approaches to these questions, one moral and the other political. While the moral approach has its inherent appeal, I am no longer convinced that it can be sustained. Its answers and the methods by which it arrives at them are, so to speak, too facile. As applied to the current controversy over America’s interrogation regime, for example, its argument is too short: torture is morally impermissible; therefore, it is politically illegitimate. On the other hand, the political approach, though it arrives at the same negative conclusion, avoids this problem by correctly bringing more considerations into the fold while at the same time, in a way I’ll describe, integrating the moral point of view--but in a subordinate role to which morality is not accustomed. I'm not entirely convinced by the political approach, and neither am I entirely clear what it involves, but it strikes me as more relevant and applicable to our heterogeneous political world.

The most common approach to human rights is expressly moralistic. It rests on a moral picture of human beings, and sets to answer our questions by reference to violations which would undermine or constrain human beings (as painted by that picture). This approach is moralistic partly because it places moral characteristics front and center, particularly dignity and autonomy. Additionally, the approach wants to understand the concept of human rights as a moral concept. The study of human rights is fundamentally the study of a part of morality; and, the application of a human right requires only a recognition of the relevant moral principles in conjunction with a perception of the salient moral reasons.

On this approach, all one needs to evaluate the legitimacy of a political decision is to know its moral standing.

For some time now, I’ve found this moralistic approach laudatory. The connection between morality and a human rights violation, crudely put, is this: a political activity constitutes a human rights violation whenever it expresses a morally illegitimate exercise of political authority. This formula allows us to arrive at an assessment of political activities in a ‘pure’ manner, expressly setting aside all irrelevant considerations, i.e. all non-moral considerations. Moreover, since morality takes itself to apply everywhere rational activity exists, the approach’s scope is basically total and unconstrained. That is, anyone can transport the moral viewpoint, correctly construed, and use it to judge political activity wherever and whenever it exists.

As operating on political institutions and its activities, the moralistic approach has the great and heavily advertised advantage of being outside of what it judges. Often and clearly so, this is the correct standpoint. For example, this external view constrains the human tendency to exaggerate the weight and importance of self-serving considerations, e.g. nationalistic ones. Another advantage is morality’s integrity or holism. The univocal nature of its pronouncements and its refusal to countenance compromise are what make morality so beautiful and appealing.

This is nicely exemplified, for example, in the character of Socrates. Unlike all true statesmen, Socrates cares little that a political decision is necessary to save the state if that decision is, judged from the standpoint of the moral virtues, wrong. He couldn’t make any such decision because, being the virtuous man he was, he couldn’t see the reasons in favor of it. Most of us understand Socrates’ moral incapacities as virtues, and we have a strong tendency to judge political life from this perspective. We recoil, for example, when we witness President Obama’s evident betrayal of Senator Obama’s promises on government transparency. We applaud, on the other hand, the alacrity with which he announced the closure of Guantanamo (but, let us not forget, not Bagram). Here the expressions of blame and praise spring from the same moral source. Just as lying for political gain warrants moral repugnance, curbing torture deserves moral praise.

Our admiration for Socrates’ integrity should not blind us, however, to what it sacrifices. In particular, Socrates understood that he could never be a politician. He predicted that his inability to compromise, operating within the political, would have meant an even quicker death than he actually suffered. We can learn something here. I believe Socrates rightly sensed the deep incompatibility between moralism and the political. His a(nti-) political stance isn’t just a peculiar fact about himself, it belies the thought that the political can be adequately evaluated by just the moral standpoint. If so, then the moral incapacities which are so valuable to correct individual behavior become vices in political decision-making.

Is there another approach?

The philosopher, Bernard Williams, constructed a concise, expressly political, formulation of what constitutes a fundamentally illegitimate policy: (roughly) any governmental policy the effect of which makes the existence of government worse than its absence. Government exists to solve and resolve certain basic social problems; but, when its policies make government appreciably worse than the problem, that amounts to a paradigm case of a human rights violation. In short, when political authority approximates unmediated coercive power, we have an illegitimate exercise of state power; we have a human rights violation.

It is a weakness of our current human rights regime that, philosophically, it is grounded in moral concepts like human dignity and autonomy. Although morally powerful, these concepts are politically stunted (especially in America which has made no explicit use of them). Williams’s political formulation avoids this problem because, like his ethical approach in general, it embraces minimalism and avoids moralism. It does this by working only with concepts like power, coercion and authority. These are taken to be non-moral concepts which nevertheless any conceivable political construction must employ. Even if it is true that criminals or terrorists have no dignity, and that no accommodation is made for an individual's moral autonomy, we can still hold that, in its ambitions, a government can overreach and, in taking action, make itself more monstrous than the problem its ambitions attempt to resolve. Anyone can make this comparative judgment, irrespective of their substantive moral standpoint.

Even an amoral fanatic like Dick Cheney recognizes this. You can see it in how he defends the interrogation regime no doubt he had a hand in shaping and making into policy. In numerous interviews, Cheney virtually contemns moral considerations emphasizing instead the mantra that his methods directly helped thwart untold (literally, since the details of the supposed upside were, and continue to be, conveniently classified) number of attacks. If he's telling the truth, it would at least render intelligible how Bush’s government did not make itself worse than the problem. This is true even if it does not make the regime any more morally acceptable, for his is not an attempt at moral justification. Cheney’s defense is expressly political and offers a story (Williams calls this type of story a legitimation story) for how an interrogation regime can take the shape his did and yet maintain its legitimacy. In particular, this story places great stress on the necessary connection between these policies and the basic responsibility of government to protect its citizens.

As I suggested, the moral approach to assessing a Cheney-style legitimation story is too quick. Since no decent human being could help but arrive at the conclusion that torture is morally repugnant and hence wrong to do no matter the context, adopting this viewpoint leaves us with the puzzle of how a regime taking this shape could sustain itself over so many years and even after the facts about the nature of the interrogations have been known for nearly 5 years. Since ignorance of the morally relevant facts is not at issue, the only way out of the puzzle is to point to a virulent moral weakness induced by fear. For reasons I cannot get into, I find this utterly implausible.

The political approach’s evaluation goes beyond a narrow moral assessment of the interrogations themselves. It takes in all the political conditions required to make interrogations of this type possible. In the case of our torture regime, here are some of them. At the highest levels of government (not to mention the lower levels), generally there existed a pervasive and mendacious secrecy; unendingly imaginative forms of obfuscation and, when these failed, outright lies were told to Congress, to the courts, to foreign governments, to domestic and international organizations, and to the American public; powerful and influential members of Congress colluded with the executive to maintain the regime as well as pass laws designed to offer legal cover for its criminal acts; international covenants the US ratified were repeatedly violated and, in general, our moral and legal obligations were repeatedly and maliciously ignored, thereby making a mockery of international law; when they weren’t kept completely in the dark, institutions like the press, the OLC and the DOJ were subverted and/or used to propagandize; and, in sum, the domestic law and, really, our entire legal tradition was turned on its head and perverted.

All this is interconnected and interlocked to support the government’s project to manufacture the authority needed for its interrogation regime. When we have all of this before us, it is difficult to see how the Bush/Cheney government did not make itself worse than the problem it attempted to solve. The secrecy with which it carried out its policies points to the explanation for its illegitimacy. In particular, it rests to a large extent on how we understand ourselves here and now: no modern legitimation story can depend on the belief that political good and the means to it are the sole provenance of political authority. So, even if we are charitable and entertain the notion that the principal architects of this government aimed at the benefit of the citizenry, to protect us—if necessary, from ourselves—that alone wouldn’t serve to legitimize anything (this remains true even if, more fantastically, the regime served to actually protect us). This is a political and not a moral explanation, but through it we can see how the political can acknowledge the moral. It does so not necessarily as an independent constraint (that would be moralism all over again), but rather because its field of operation can, and in our case does, involve beings whose self-understanding includes morality. Lastly, this helps explain why Machiavellianism, although it can make a temporary appearance, can’t really work for us. Only a fanatic can suggest that we should just discard the moral understanding of ourselves and return to a ‘simpler’ time (if it ever existed) during which statesmen, with their good intentions, could run things without running them by citizens. This is fanaticism, not because it is immoral (although that’s a conceivable reason), but rather because any such suggestion is now beyond the political pale. If it is to exist at all, it must hide and remain underground, just as the interrogation regime and its instigators have been doing. And as with all forms of fanaticism, killing it doesn’t require moral arguments, but rather a spotlight.

Read More...

Wednesday, April 8, 2009

Let's do it


birds do it
bees do it
even educated fleas do it
let's do it...

Former president of Peru, Alberto Fujimora, convicted and sentenced to 25 years in his own country for human rights violations.  It's a first in history.  Essentially, he was convicted on charges of authorizing kidnapping, torture and murder.  Sound familiar?  (For the murder part, see Seymour Hersh's assertions about Cheney's assassination squads, here.) 

Who's next?  Let's do it.

Read More...

Tuesday, April 7, 2009

Full IC Red Cross report

Now leaked in full at the New York Review of Books. Go here.

For Mark Danner's companion article, 'The Red Cross Torture Report: What it Means', go here.

Danner's article is worth reading, so don't miss it.

It's hard to see how this document will not have significant political ramifications. Hopefully, all the investigations that have been shelved and put into abeyance will be fast tracked.

As Danner points out in his article, the contours of the Bush administration's torture program have been known since 2004. What more needs to be revealed before action is taken?

Obama continues to assert that he wants to move forward. Moving forward is appropriate under certain circumstances, but in this case it is unequivocally the wrong path. This is not only because the current administration has no standing to 'forgive' and forget (only the victims have that authority), it is evident that the issue won't just pass away. Not only are many Americans rightfully vociferous on this issue, it has a determined international following. Even if America should allow its politicians to continually obfuscate, the rest of the world will not. Specifically Spain, the UK and Poland are now undertaking investigations.

In this case, the only way forward is to look backward and come to grips with what we have done and what it means for us. To do that, we need a full accounting.

Read More...

Thursday, April 2, 2009

Ward Churchill's Victory

After more than two years of trial, the University of Colorado was found guilty of wrongful termination in the case versus Ward Churchill. Though claiming academic integrity reasons, it is by all lights clear that the University of Colorado dismissed Churchill due to an article he wrote in 2005 about the terrorist attacks of 2001. In that article, Churchill suggested the view that the terrorist attacks were not simply a case of targeting innocent civilians but that they were strategically aimed at the financial structure of the military machine of the US. Let me say a few comments about this decision.

1) It is unacceptable that the New York Times is so shamelessly biassed on the issue. When the reputation of the powerful is at stake the New York Times walks on eggshells despite all evidence against them ("Scooter" Libby got a lot more deference from the New York Times). But when the reputation of an unpopular, marginal and powerless professor is at stake the New York Times comes out of the house, bat in hand, to beat up on him and please its enraged readers. Thanks again New York Times for courageously defending the truth...

2) The issue is not a dispute between freedom of speech and academic integrity, as the New York Times says. It is entirely about academic freedom. Churchill advanced a view that may not be true but which is perfectly conceivable. As such, it should be judged dispassionately aside from nationalistic sentiments. If found lacking, one should not be offended by its falsity. Plus, it presents the terrible events of 9/11 in a different light which arguably provides insight into the psychological motivations of Islamic terrorists--whether or not their motivations are justifiable. Furthermore, having no apparent Arab roots or connections with Al Qaeda, it is hard to explain Churchill's article as a conspiracy to destabilize the US. It seems to be the spontaneous work of a fellow who has a particularly critical view of his own country.

3) Finally, it is conspicuous that the jury was so intent on giving Churchill no economic reparation for the years he has been unemployed. Unable to award him no money while finding the University of Colorado guilty, they granted him a symbolic $1. They went as far as to ask the judge if they could grant such a ludicrous amount with the opposition of only one member and, when answered negatively, if they could simply replace that member. Pending further clarification, it gives the unfortunate impression that the jury was trying to apply the law reluctantly.

Read More...

blogger templates